Course Description

The conventional story on war- and peacemaking almost always speaks of great deeds by Great Men. It tells how genius generals win wars and how skillful diplomats strike peace deals; how heroic soldiers fight and how selfless peacemakers unite; and, crucially, how wars end where peace begins and vice versa. Inspired by Tolstoy’s narrative of war as an assemblage of serendipity and chance, this course will look at war/peace beyond the lens of rationality and of strategic interests. Following Latour’s reading of Tolstoy, it will introduce a less anthropocentric and – hopefully - more pluralistic perspective by allowing other actors to make peace/war, such as UN reports and US drones, reconciliation workshops and surveillance techniques, etc. Building on Foucault’s inversion of Clausewitz, it will explore war as a general grid through which modern society can be analyzed even – and especially - during so-called peacetime.

Wednesday, February 12, 2014

Hannah Berwian, entry no. 3 (Latour)

According to Latour, just like Tolstoy’s “great man” have unduly received the praise for big victories in history, so are individual scientist singled out to stand for scientific revolutions that have only been enabled, achieved its prominence and credibility, through a complex interplay of social and scientific forces and agents. In the first part of “The Pasteurization of France” from 1993, Bruno Latour offers a thorough critique of constructivist sociology that tries to explain scientific facts merely in terms of their social construction. Instead, he emphasis that sciences can neither be reduced to its technical content nor to its social context. Relinquishing any a priori ontological assumptions, it has to be understood in conjunction of the two aspects that constitute and define each other as well as the relevant actors. Through the semiotic inspection of scientific literature Latour illustrates his thesis by means of the seemingly indisputable achievements of French hygienist at the end of the 19. century, a victory that has come to be incarnated by one single name: ”Pasteur”. However, given Latour’s expressed desire to avoid the predefinition of actors it is striking that the inspection of three academic journals already presupposes a vision of which actors may be important and where they can be found and who is to define them.

Latour argues that the hygienist as a social movement provided the necessary space, motivation and a receptive and uncritical audience for Pasteur’s endeavour in the laboratory. Offering the infrastructure, they acted as a kind of translator. Especially the discourse connecting the health of the poor with the wealth of the rich was designed to find support in left and right circles.
The Pasteurian’s work offered a long sought solution to the mysteries of contagiousness by shedding light on the role of a hitherto invisible but highly influential group of social agents, the microbes. The microbes could explain for the unintended consequences beyond human understanding such as the import of cholera through pilgrims. It seems that Tolstoy would use this example as a proof that things we attribute to chance, genius or free will are simply due to our limited understanding and proposes sciences as the means to reveal mysteries, as the new God so to say. However, Latour shows that the adaption of sciences leads to similar unjustified glorification of “geniuses” that Tolstoy had criticised in Napoleon.
Moreover, he argues that the ubiquity of the microbes required and thus justified the ubiquity health agents to take care of them. This shows how the explanatory power of the microbes is harnessed to reconstruct public power and social relations. In other words, they offered to their representatives, the Pasteurians, a new source of power and authority. As Foucault may argue the phenomena of the microbe was not purposely created to establish certain forms of social control and domination. Rather, it emerged more or less arbitrarily as a potential source of power and was consequently appropriated for biopolitical purposes. What is interesting in terms of Latour’s conception of war is that he includes non-human agents, such as the microbes as possible wagers and enemies in war.

In this piece it remains unclear whether Latour disagrees fundamentally with Tolstoy’s demand to submit to sciences as the new authority. His emphasis lies on showing that from a methodological point of view, neither social relations nor sciences can be analysed in isolation from or reduced to the other by revealing that a variety of social forces were paramount to give Pasteur’s findings and name the meaning and impact that is associated with them today. At the same time, Latour does not explicitly put the merit or objectivity of scientific findings itself into questions.
In his more recent lecture “War and peace in an age of ecological conflict” Latour doesn’t display how certain scientific facts have gained their prominence through particular ideological constellations. He is more worried about how the means of constructivist critique are abused by contemporary climate change sceptics to discredit what he considers to be important scientific findings about the threatening progression of global warming. In terms of the climate change debate the God of sciences cannot be appealed to to settle the dispute as the sciences act as the very ground on which the battle is fought out. Indeed, in absence of a common authority Latour describes the current state as a state of war.
He organizes his argument around three dividing lines: Firstly, the rationalist claim that presupposes a scientific consensus before decisions on policy responses can follow. The climate change debate exposes the fundamental flaw of the rationalist model that assumes science to be capable to unify in light of objective, dispassionate, scientific evidence.  Rather, subjectivity, biases and passion define the agenda when the scientific research is so inextricably linked to human activities that can have themselves immediate impact on the findings and vice versa. This point constitutes the second division: the “anthropocene” accepting the inseparability of social and natural factors versus the “Holocene” disposing ecological conflicts as distant and outside of the human realm.

The last cleavage reflects the preceding ones and puts the capacity of natural sciences to act as a unifying authority into question. Are the disagreeing parties in a state of war or is there a neutral referee to decide upon our disagreement? Are we in need of politics or policies? Latour takes a clear stands on all the three division allying with the I.P.C.C. and the urgent need to act upon it. However, as long as we find ourselves trapped in a war about the overarching legitimating authority it seems the necessary policy action that is so urgent is postponed till the victory is gained. As Latour concedes there is no “masterplan without a master”. The framework of politics needs to be reconstituted but until this projects is realized against the powerful capitalist interest that are willing to invest enormous amounts of money to establish contradictory scientific data it may as well be too late. Latour’s appeal to, step by step composition of a “common world” resembles the call of French blogger and author Thierry Crouzet for “commonism”[1] as an ethics of sharing. However, Couzet argues that “commonism” is to be to be realized in a capitalist framework. Yet, maintaining the institution of private property seems to represent a contradiction to the principle of the “commons” themselves. The Slovenian philosopher Slavoy Zizek faces this incompatibility. Accordingly, the fundamental issue of the capitalist system is that it is unable to deal with not only the commons of external nature but similar those of human culture and internal nature, such as biogenetics. What he hence proposes is a “new kind of communism”[2] (unlike Couzet with a traditional “u”), communist in the sense that “we care about the commons”. Hence, what Latour does leave open is how this war is meant to be fought and how the fundamental changes he demands in the conception of politics can be realized. Ecological utopians, as Zizek would say, are not those who asks for a radical change in human lifestyle and organization. Utopians are those who sustain the illusion that we can face the issue of the commons through gradual adaption paired with scientific progress nourishing the enlightenment idea of nature as an object of human domination.

No comments:

Post a Comment